C. S. LEWIS: THE ABOLITION OF MAN (1943)
A Summary, followed by a Brief Summary
by Arend Smilde
See also “Quotations & Allusions in The Abolition of Man”
PDF – fit to print
as a six-page, A5-format booklet
I
There is a
widespread modern assumption that value judgments do not reflect any objective reality.
For example, the authors of a textbook on English “for the upper forms of
schools” tell their pupils that language as we use it involves continual
“confusion” because, as they say, we often “appear to be saying something very
important about something: and actually we are only saying something about our
own feelings.” On this view, someone calling a waterfall “sublime” or calling
his horse a “willing servant” is saying nothing about the waterfall or the
horse, but “only” about his own emotions. One objection to this is that the
authors fail to do what they might be expected to do – teaching English by
discussing the difference between good ways and bad ways to express emotions.
What is worse is that they invariably approach feelings as being “only feelings”, thus breeding in their
pupils a general contempt or suspicion toward sentiment. This may not be their
intention: they “may be perfectly ready to admit that a good education should
build some sentiments while destroying others.” However, “it is the ‘debunking’
side of their work, and this side alone, which will really tell.” Any success
on the positive side is precluded by the modern “educational predicament”.
The predicament results from the
modern assumption about value judgments. This assumption is now indeed
widespread, but it is in fact a novelty in human history. Until quite recently,
humans believed that their emotional responses to outside realities could be
either true or false (“congruous” or “incongruous”) to those realities. “True”
emotions were reflections of objective value. Emotions did not supplant reason
but they could conform to it and needed to be trained to do so. Educating
children included training them to have the right emotional responses and get
rid of wrong ones – so that they would not, as adults, have to rely only on
Reason in their pursuit of goodness, beauty and truth; for Reason by itself
moves nothing.
The new outlook, in contrast, fails to
recognize that human sentiment could ever be congruent or incongruent to outside
realities; sentiment cannot be reasonable or even unreasonable. The role of
emotions is that of mere fogs between us and the world of objective facts, “a
world without one trace of value”.
Modern educators are thus faced with a
choice between two evils. They must either try to remove all sentiments from
the pupil’s mind, or else “encourage some sentiments for reasons that have
nothing to do with their intrinsic ‘justness’.” The latter procedure would be
cynical propaganda, which perhaps many will abhor. Abhorrence is a sentiment
and therefore, on the current view, invalid. Nevertheless it often prevails.
What then remains is the other evil: wholesale debunking of all sentiment.
This, however, is not less disastrous: it amounts to a kind of “atrophy of the
chest”, or amputation of the “heart”. “Without the aid of trained emotions the
intellect is powerless against the animal organism.” Even supposing that “the
harder virtues could really be theoretically justified with no appeal to
objective value (...) it still remains true that no justification of virtue
will enable a man to be virtuous.”
II
Using the
Chinese word Tao (“the Way”) for the
realm of objective value as the basis for traditional morality, we can say that
modern humanity, in adopting “subjectivism about values”, has assumed a
position “outside the Tao”. The
position entails, as we saw, a choice between two evils (cynical propaganda and
wholesale debunking); and one or the other evil is our fate if we believe that
the Tao does not exist. But quite
apart from such practical considerations, there are theoretical difficulties to
this position.
The wish to abandon traditional
morality is often linked with what is supposed to be a new, “realistic” or
“rational” or “basic” set of values. The new values usually boil down to the
preservation of society or humanity. This is, however, not a new value; it is
as old as any other value and a part of the Tao.
And it is hard to see where else any values could be found than in the Tao, i.e. how they could, in the last
resort, be other than objective. The reasoning that serves to debunk
traditional morality is the sort of reasoning that will never reach practical
conclusions. It can only produce statements of fact, such as “This will
preserve society”; it will never attain to the insight that “Society ought to
be preserved”. Nor will it be helped by any appeal to “Instinct”. To have
spontaneous urges can never by itself mean that we ought to follow them. What
is more, the urge to ensure a long and happy future for “humanity”, if that
urge exists at all, is just one among many competing instincts, most of them
very much stronger, such as the urge to preserve one’s own individual life or
immediate offspring. Some guideline from outside the realm of instinct is indispensable
for deciding which instinct is to be obeyed to which extent.
Thus practical principles cannot be
reached as conclusions: they are premisses. On the
other hand, when one premiss is recognized, the
validity of the Tao is implicitly
recognized; which is to say that all the other premisses
must then also be valid. If there is, for example, a duty to posterity, then it
is impossible to see why there should not be an equally binding duty to
parents. Any attempt to discard the Tao
and introduce new values must be based on “fragments from the Tao itself, arbitrarily wrenched from
their context in the whole and then swollen to madness in their isolation, yet
still owing to the Tao and to it
alone such validity as they possess.” – “The human mind has no more power of
inventing a new value than of imagining a new primary colour,
or, indeed, of creating a new sun and a new sky for it to move in.”
The Tao is not “an unchanging code given once for all”; it does admit
development from within through self-criticism, or “internal criticism”. External
criticism – a demand that any traditional value should “produce its
credentials, as though the burden of proof lay on it” – is beside the point
because criticism from outside the Tao
removes itself from any basis on which it can assert values, even its own value
as criticism.
Even so, modern people are unlikely to
see the Tao as something to be obeyed
“in stupid reverence”; they will rather view it as a “psychological survival”
from all previous human history and prehistory. Values are, on this view, just
another piece of Nature to be conquered sooner or later by applied science.
When this happens, we humans will no longer be in the grip of obscure “ideas of
what we ought to do” since these very
ideas will be in our grip. We will then produce and change such ideas at our
own convenience. – There are no theoretical difficulties here like those of the
Innovator’s position, since this rejection of value does not itself depend on
value. Here is a real rejection of the whole concept of value. It remains to
consider what must happen if this particular triumph of applied science comes
about.
III
The power of
humans to do what they like seems to be growing all the time through humanity’s
so-called “conquest of Nature” – the progress of applied science. However,
“each new power won by man is a power
over man as well.” We can throw bombs
from airplanes but can also be bombed ourselves; a race of birth-controllers is
a race whose own birth has been controlled. So it is worth asking exactly whose
power grows as Nature is being conquered. It is, in fact, the power of that
very small minority of people who are in actual control of the forces of
Nature. The great majority of mankind becomes more and more powerless against
this minority; and “if any one age really attains, by eugenics and scientific
education, the power to make its descendants what it pleases, all men who live
after it are the patients of that power.” As the Conqueror of Nature, the human
race is not only “the general who triumphs” but “also the prisoner who follows
the triumphal car.”
The final stage will have come when
“humanity” has obtained full control over itself. “Human nature will be the last part of Nature to surrender to Man.”
The ruling minority will have become a caste of Conditioners, people “who
really can cut out posterity in what shape they please.” From this moment
onward, the human conscience will work the way humans want it to work – that is, the way wanted by the Conditioners. What
are the Conditioners going to want in conditioning our consciences, and,
indeed, how are they going to want anything? Human ideas about good and evil,
duty and taboo, are among the things for them to decide about and therefore
cannot serve as a ground for their decision. All motives for human action have
become objects of choice and manipulation by Conditioners; so the Conditioners
themselves are left without any motives. Unless they stop moving and acting at
all, they must become prey to any force that just happens to put them in motion – in other words, to irrational,
natural impulses. And since their power is perfectly effective, the human race
will for the rest of its existence be subjected to such forces of nature as
happen to have acted upon the Conditioners. Man’s conquest of Nature will have
brought about Nature’s conquest of Man: the Abolition of Man.
Man’s conquest of Nature has in one
sense been a surrender to Nature ever since the birth of modern science. For
whatever is conquered, or even deemed to be conquerable, is reckoned to belong
in the realm of Nature – and thus in a way surrendered to it. The surrender may
require some “repression of elements in what would otherwise be our total
reaction” to what we are conquering; perhaps most conspicuously so in the case
of vivisection. This price always can, and usually is, argued to be worth
paying. – “But as soon as we take the final step of reducing our own species to
the level of mere Nature, the whole process is stultified, for this time the
being who stood to gain and the being who has been sacrificed are one and the
same.”
To call the final stage a “magician’s
bargain” (give up your soul in return for power) is not just one possible
metaphor: it is a welcome reminder of the common impulse from which both
science and magic sprang in early modern times. Magic failed and science
succeeded; but they were engaged in the same enterprise, namely “to extend
Man’s power to the performance of all things possible.” A genuine and
disinterested love of knowledge no doubt played a vital part in the success of
science; “in every mixed movement the efficacy comes from the good elements not
from the bad. But the presence of the bad elements is not irrelevant to the
direction the efficacy takes.” The “chief trumpeter of the modern era”, Francis
Bacon, was strikingly close to Marlowe’s Dr Faustus in regarding wealth and
power as the true goal of knowledge.
Meanwhile the scientists themselves
may well be willing to avoid a final stage of applied science which would be
the undoing of all previous stages. In reducing humanity and human conscience
to manipulable Nature, they would be scrapping the
value of knowledge along with all other values. But “perhaps, in the nature of
things, analytical understanding must always be a basilisk which kills what it
sees and only sees by killing”; and “if the scientists themselves cannot arrest
this process before it reaches the common Reason and kills that too, then
someone else must arrest it.” – “You cannot go on ‘seeing through’ things for
ever. The whole point of seeing through something is to see something through
it. (...) To ‘see through’ all things is the same as not to see.”
A Brief Summary of The
Abolition of Man
I – By regarding all value judgments
as subjective, modern humans are faced with a choice between two evils. Either
you hope that other people will still believe at least some value judgments to
be objective; or you hope they will not. The first alternative must involve
cynical propaganda. This may in practice be often rejected for moral reasons,
although on the subjectivist assumption this comes from a confusion of thought.
The second alternative means a debunking of all our sense of value. The
resulting apathy is felt to be highly inconvenient, and found to be incurable.
II – The attempt to debunk
traditional values is often based on a set of values which is considered to be
new, but which in fact is a small selection from traditional morality. The
innovator will be unable, in the end, to explain why this selection is retained
while the rest is rejected. Thus on a closer view he will have confirmed the
“given” nature of all moral principles and the need to reject either all or
nothing of traditional morality. Modern people who admit this are then likely
not to accept all, but to reject all, since they believe that morality is
human; that humanity is nature; and that nature is a thing to rule, not to be
ruled by.
III – “Man’s conquest of
Nature” will be completed when human
nature is conquered. Values will then be a thing for humans to produce and to
modify at will, not a thing to be guided by. The only force left to motivate us
will be the force of natural impulses. Man’s conquest of nature will thus have
ended in man’s total surrender to nature. On the assumption of a perfect
genetic science perfectly applied, we may expect this surrender to be
irreversible. Our wish to “see through” the mainspring of specifically human
action is a magician’s bargain: “to ‘see through’ all things is the same as not
to see.”
last revised
on 3 June 2015